Art promotion by the Bloomsbury Group: 2. Clive Bell and Significant Form

Roger Fry (1866–1934), Clive Bell (c 1924), oil on canvas, 73.4 x 60.0 cm, The National Portrait Gallery, London. Courtesy of the National Portrait Gallery, via Wikimedia Commons.

Roger Fry may have been the leading art historian, critic, and painter in the Bloomsbury group, but it was Clive Bell who laid down the aesthetic theory which underpinned the group’s thrust to change the direction of art in the twentieth century.

Clive Bell (1850-1942) was born into a wealthy family, which had made its money from coal mines in Wiltshire, England, and Merthyr Tydfil in South Wales. He read history at Cambridge University, after which he was awarded a scholarship to study in Paris, where he became interested in art, and by his own account ‘became familiar with the modern French masters’, including Cézanne, Gauguin, and Matisse. He married the painter Vanessa Stephen, who was Virginia Woolf’s sister, in 1907, and became a core member of the Bloomsbury group.

He wrote his first book, titled simply Art, in 1913, in which he expounded his aesthetic philosophy in the context of art, its history and appreciation, which I discuss below.

The group as a whole took a liberal socialist approach to society, supporting the campaign for women’s right to vote. However others have seen Bell as remaining a snob and hedonist. During the First World War he was a pacifist, and he was allowed to work on a farm instead of being called up to serve in the Armed Forces.

In 1911, his marriage began to collapse, when Vanessa started an affair with Roger Fry, and by the end of the war she was living with Duncan Grant, and Bell had had a number of affairs. Despite that their marriage was never annulled, and he often spent periods in the rural farmhouse where Duncan, Vanessa, and their three children lived.

Bell and Fry shared a vigorous enthusiasm for what Fry had termed ‘Post-Impressionism’. As an art historian and painter, Fry contributed his expertise in those areas, while Bell concentrated on theory, particularly aesthetics. Art (1914) was widely read, and is still actively discussed. Among his later books, Since Cézanne (1922) and An Account of French Painting (1931) are also relevant.

Art (1914)

You can download the complete text of this book from Project Gutenberg, or Archive.org.

In its introduction, Bell claims that he and Fry “still disagree profoundly” about the principles of aesthetics, something not borne out by Fry’s writings.

IF
Mosaic of Theodora – Basilica of San Vitale (built A.D. 547), Italy. UNESCO World heritage site. By Petar Milošević, via Wikimedia Commons.

Bell’s choice of illustrations is also very telling:

  • a 5th century Wei dynasty (before 534 CE) figure from China,
  • an 11th century Persian dish,
  • an early Peruvian pot,
  • a 6th century Byzantine mosaic from San Vitale, Ravenna, (above)
  • Cézanne’s Maison devant la Sainte-Victoire près de Gardanne (1886–90), (below)
  • and an early painting by Picasso.
cézannemaisondevantmtstvictoire
Paul Cézanne (1839-1906), Maison devant la Sainte-Victoire près de Gardanne (1886–90), oil on canvas, 65.5 x 81.3 cm, Indianapolis Museum of Art, Indianapolis, IN. Wikimedia Commons.

His concept of art is thoroughly elitist: only certain people are capable of “personal experience of a peculiar emotion” when they are confronted by works of art, those who are “sensitive”. Those objects that provoke this particular emotion in such sensitive people “we call works of art”. Late in the book he writes: “A sure sensibility in visual art is at least as rare as a good ear for music.”

So what is it in a work of art which provokes aesthetic emotion? Bell states that it is “significant form”. By this he means “lines and colours combined in a particular way, certain forms and relations of forms”, which he considers provoke aesthetic emotion.

Many critics have pointed out the hopeless circularity of his ‘definitions’, which therefore fail to clarify anything. Bell also admits that “the objects which provoke aesthetic emotion vary with each individual”, which he accepts is a matter of taste. However he sees it as the role of a critic to guide the viewer to experience aesthetic emotion, and thereby the viewer will judge an object to be a work of art.

Later in the book he offers criteria for distinguishing ‘good’ and ‘bad’ drawing: “What we mean when we speak of ‘good drawing’ and ‘bad drawing’ is not doubtful; we mean ‘aesthetically moving’ and ‘aesthetically insignificant.’ Why some drawing moves and some does not is a very different question.” And one which he does not answer except to refer us back to his circular concept of ‘significant form’.

One potential test which he provides is that “people who cannot feel pure aesthetic emotions remember pictures by their subjects; whereas people who can, as often as not, have no idea what the subject of a picture is. They have never noticed the representative element, and so when they discuss pictures they talk about the shapes of forms and the relations and quantities of colours. Often they can tell by the quality of a single line whether or no[t] a man is a good artist.”

This is, perhaps, a succinct expression of the formalist approach, and an excellent explanation as to why it fails so thoroughly.

If Bell deprives us of any meaningful definitions, he does not hold back in informing us what he, as an aesthete and critic, deems to be art, and what is mere illustration or visual trifles.

Examples of true art, in Bell’s judgement, include:

  • the works illustrated in the book,
  • Giotto’s frescoes at Padua,
  • paintings by Poussin, Claude Lorraine, El Greco, Rembrandt (but see below), Velasquez, Vermeer, Rubens, Jordaens, Chardin, Ingres, Corot, Daumier, Manet, Renoir, Degas,
  • paintings by Piero della Francesca, and several contemporaries,
  • paintings by Cézanne, Gauguin, van Gogh, Matisse, Picasso,
  • most works known as ‘Primitive’,
  • only 3-4% of Cubist or Impressionist paintings,
  • paintings by Duncan Grant and Roger Fry.

Examples of what is not art include:

  • Frith’s Paddington Station (here)
  • “descriptive pictures”, which imitate nature, including most realist paintings,
  • the paintings of most Royal Academicians, including Lord Leighton,
  • most painters “who flourished between the high Renaissance and the contemporary movement may be divided into two classes, virtuosi and dunces”, neither of which he deems to be art,
  • JMW Turner, who is dismissed as “an after-dinner poet”,
  • John Singer Sargent,
  • Neo-Impressionists, including Seurat, Signac, and Cross.
Rembrandt Harmenszoon van Rijn, A Woman bathing in a Stream (1654), oil on panel, 61.8 x 47 cm, National Gallery, London. Wikimedia Commons.
Rembrandt Harmenszoon van Rijn, A Woman bathing in a Stream (1654), oil on panel, 61.8 x 47 cm, National Gallery, London. Wikimedia Commons.

His comments on Rembrandt are particularly scathing: “Rembrandt, indeed, perhaps the greatest genius of them [17th century masters] all, is a typical ruin of his age. For, except in a few of his later works, his sense of form and design is utterly lost in a mess of rhetoric, romance, and chiaroscuro. It is difficult to forgive the seventeenth century for what it made of Rembrandt’s genius.”

cézannepathmasjoliechâteaunoir1902
Paul Cézanne (1839–1906), Sous-bois (Wood) (1900–02), oil on canvas, 81 x 64.5 cm, Fondation Beyeler, Riehen/Basel, Switzerland. Wikimedia Commons.

In contrast, “Cézanne is a type of the perfect artist; he is the perfect antithesis of the professional picture-maker, or poem-maker, or music-maker. He created forms because only by so doing could he accomplish the end of his existence – the expression of his sense of the significance of form.”

The final sections of the book consist of a long socio-political proposal by which art and aesthetics could be improved, including such measures as closing all art schools, making artists’ lives a misery as beggars living on public charity alone, and much more.

fryclivebell
Roger Fry (1866–1934), Clive Bell (c 1924), oil on canvas, 73.4 x 60.0 cm, The National Portrait Gallery, London. Courtesy of the National Portrait Gallery, via Wikimedia Commons.

In the next article, I will consider how those views overlap with the views of Roger Fry, and how Fry and Bell influenced art history.